Skip to main content

The Brilliance Paradox: What Really Keeps Women and Minorities from Excelling in Academia

How a misplaced emphasis on genius subtly discourages women and Black people from certain academic fields

Credit:

Allison Seiffer

In the 1980s philosophers would sometimes speak of “the Beam”—a metaphorical spotlight of intellectual brilliance that could illuminate even the most complex philosophical conundrums. Only some lucky philosophers were ever born with the Beam, and their work represented the gold standard of the field. Anyone who lacked the Beam was forever condemned to trail behind them intellectually.

One of us (Leslie) would share this sort of story whenever we would see each other at conferences. The two of us were trained in different disciplines (Leslie in philosophy and Cimpian in psychology), but we studied similar topics, so we would get together regularly to catch up on research and talk about our experiences as members of our respective fields. Psychology and philosophy are quite similar in their substance (in fact, psychology was a branch of philosophy until the mid-1800s), but the stories we told painted a picture of two fields with vastly different views on what is important for success. Much more so than psychologists, philosophers value a certain kind of person—the brilliant superstar with an exceptional mind. Psychologists, in contrast, are relatively more likely to believe that the leading lights in their field grew to achieve their positions through hard work and experience.

At first, we viewed philosophy’s obsession with brilliance as a quirk—a little strange but innocuous. Other things seemed to present bigger problems in Leslie’s field, such as its inability to attract women and minorities. Despite sustained attention to issues of underrepresentation in recent years and some efforts to alleviate them, women still accounted for fewer than 30 percent of the doctoral degrees granted in philosophy in 2015, and Black people made up only 1 percent of philosophy Ph.D.s. The field of psychology, in contrast, has been quite successful in attracting and retaining women (more than 70 percent of newly minted Ph.D.s), and Black people held 6 percent of its 2015 doctoral degrees. Admittedly, these figures still fall short of their share of the general population, but they are nonetheless six times the ratio in philosophy.

We could not wrap our minds around the discrepancy. Our fields have so much in common—both philosophers and psychologists ask questions about how people perceive and understand the world, how they decide between right and wrong, how they learn and use language, and so on. Even the few salient differences—such as psychologists’ greater use of statistics and randomized experiments—are becoming blurred nowadays with the huge increase in the popularity of experimental philosophy, in which philosophers conduct surveys and experiments to explore different perspectives on morality, for example. How could two such closely related fields be so vastly different in membership?

A Brilliant Idea

The closest thing either of us has ever had to a eureka moment came some years ago when we connected two threads running through the anecdotes we had been sharing. We were having dinner with a group of philosophers and psychologists at a conference, and the conversation happened to turn, in quick succession, from philosophers’ infatuation with brilliance to the gender gap in their field. This chance juxtaposition brought to mind for us a connection we had never considered before: maybe the premium that philosophers place on brilliance is actually the reason so few of their colleagues are women or minorities. We did not discount the benefits of brilliance. Rather we wondered whether genius was more easily overlooked in women and Black people. Could it be that insistence on the need for a keen intellect in a particular field was tantamount to hanging a “Keep Out” sign to discourage any newcomers who did not resemble that field’s current members?

On the surface, an emphasis on brilliance does not favor one group over another; cognitive ability is not tied to gender or race. Philosophers seek a certain quality of mind—regardless of whose mind it is. This seemingly logical preference quickly becomes problematic, however, in light of certain shared societal notions that incorrectly associate superior intellect with some groups—for example, white males—more than others.

Expectations of Brilliance Underlie Gender Distributions across Academic Disciplines
Credit: Jen Christiansen; Source: “Expectations of Brilliance Underlie Gender Distributions across Academic Disciplines,” by Sarah-Jane Leslie et al., in Science, Vol. 347; January 16, 2015

Even among the academics present that night, one of the views expressed was that men and women just thought differently. Women were alleged to be more practical and anchored in reality, whereas men were more willing to engage in the kind of counterfactual, abstract reasoning that is viewed as a sign of philosophical brilliance. We started to wonder whether such stereotypes, which amount to equating brilliance with men, might well dissuade women from entering a field that holds this quality in high esteem. Moreover, current members of such a field might themselves hold different expectations about the prospects of men and women and might evaluate and encourage them differently as a result. The same logic extends to race: our country has a long history of portraying Black people as intellectually inferior, which is particularly likely to affect participation in a field that focuses so single-mindedly on the quality of one’s intellect. Considering these stereotyped attitudes, which are unsupported by science, philosophy’s fascination with brilliance may have a real impact on its diversity.

Later that night the two of us talked about our insight. We speculated about whether its implications extend beyond our home disciplines. Talk of brilliance is common in academia and—it seemed to us—quite common in fields that have similar issues with diversity, such as science, technology, engineering and mathematics. Might our anecdotal comparison of philosophy and psychology have something new to say about the underrepresentation of women and minorities in these disciplines?

The more we thought about it, the more we realized that our brilliance hypothesis might also explain some of the variability in gender and race gaps among different scientific fields. For example, women make up nearly 50 percent of doctoral degrees in biochemistry but just slightly more than 30 percent of Ph.D.s in organic chemistry. The difference cannot easily be explained by the content of the fields, in which there is considerable overlap, or by their history—biochemistry emerged from organic chemistry at about the same time psychology separated out of philosophy as an independent discipline. We wondered whether the demographic differences between such sibling subjects, as well as more generally among scientific fields, could be explained in part by the extent to which they emphasize exceptional intellectual talent as the key to success.

Successful Mindsets

Our early conjectures quickly reminded us of the rich body of work developed by psychologist Carol S. Dweck of Stanford University. Dweck and her colleagues have shown that one’s beliefs about ability matter greatly for one’s ultimate success. A person who sees talent as a stable trait (a “fixed mindset” in Dweck’s terminology) is motivated to show off this aptitude and avoid mistakes, which presumably reflect the limits of that gift. In contrast, a person who adopts a “growth mindset” sees his or her current capacity as a work in progress. In other words, ability is a malleable quantity that can usually be increased with more effort and better strategies. For a person with a growth mindset, mistakes are not an indictment but rather a valuable signal highlighting which of their skills are in need of work.

Although Dweck initially studied mindsets in individuals, she and Mary Murphy, now at Indiana University Bloomington, suggested in 2010 that organized groups of people, such as companies and clubs, may also hold these sorts of views. We took that idea a step further and considered whether they might permeate entire disciplines as well. The fascination with brilliance in philosophy and other areas could conceivably create an atmosphere in which displays of intellectual prowess are rewarded and imperfections are to be avoided at all costs. In combination with the stereotypes suggesting that genius is unevenly distributed across groups, such a field-wide perspective could easily turn toxic for members of stereotyped groups, such as women or Black people. After all, it is easy to “see” imperfections and inadequacies in those people who are expected to have them.

Several long phone conversations later, we had a tentative plan for putting our ideas to the test. We would contact academic professionals from across a wide range of disciplines and ask them whether they thought that some form of exceptional intellectual talent was necessary for success in their field. We would then look up statistics on the gender and racial/ethnic composition of the people obtaining Ph.D.s in these disciplines, which the National Science Foundation freely supplies on its Web site. If our hunch was correct, we should see that those disciplines that place more value on brilliance tend to have fewer female and Black Ph.D.s. This pattern should hold not just at the macro level—when comparing the hard sciences, for example, with the social sciences and the humanities—but also within these broad domains for disciplines as similar as philosophy and psychology.

More than a year and thousands of e-mailed surveys later, we and our collaborators Meredith Meyer of Otterbein University in Ohio and Edward Freeland of Princeton University finally had an answer to some of our questions. Equal parts relieved and exhilarated, we saw that the answers received from almost 2,000 academics across 30 fields matched the distribution of Ph.D.s in the way we had expected. Fields that placed more value on brilliance also conferred fewer Ph.D.s on women and Black candidates. The greater the emphasis on this single fixed trait, the fewer doctoral degrees were awarded to either of these groups. The proportion of female and Black Ph.D.s in psychology, for example, was higher than the parallel proportions for philosophy, math or physics.

Next, we separated the responses in the physical and biological sciences from those in the humanities and social sciences. Analyses of these subgroups indicated that a stronger emphasis on brilliance correlated with fewer female and Black Ph.D.s regardless of whether we compared physics with biology or philosophy with sociology. It seemed that we had stumbled onto an explanation that was general enough to describe the representation of multiple stereotyped groups in fields across the entire academic spectrum.

Alternative Ideas

Our excitement about these data aside, all we had really shown at this point was a correlation between the presumed desirability of a fixed trait—brilliance—and a dearth of women or Black people in a given field. We had not yet demonstrated cause and effect. Certainly many other plausible explanations for the gender imbalances have been proffered over the years—from a heavier workload that favored single men and those with wives who did not work outside the home to a supposed female preference for working with living organisms, as opposed to inanimate objects. We needed to determine whether we were bringing something new to the table—perhaps our explanation reduced to one that had been previously offered.

We carefully examined the most common alternatives. For instance, did our brilliance measure simply track differences between fields in their reliance on math? We looked at the math portion of incoming students’ Graduate Record Examinations (GREs) as a proxy. Beliefs about brilliance still predicted women’s representation above and beyond those scores. Similarly, we found no support for the common view that women are underrepresented in “high-powered fields” because they prefer a better work-family balance. We asked the academics in our sample how many hours they worked per week—both on- and off-campus. Taking into account these differences in workload did not, however, reduce the explanatory power of beliefs about brilliance; this single variable still predicted the magnitude of gender gaps across the 30 disciplines. We also considered the prevalent thought that women might be more interested in working with (and have a better intuitive understanding of) people, whereas men prefer inanimate systems. But an analysis of the many branches of philosophy, for example, that do in fact consider people—and are still dominated by men—basically blew that idea out of contention.

As often happens in research, this initial study made it clear to us how much we did not yet know about the phenomenon that we were investigating. For example, we realized it would be important to know if academics’ beliefs about brilliance predict gender and race gaps at earlier points in students’ educational trajectories. We were very interested in testing our idea at the bachelor’s level, which is the gateway to students’ later careers. Do field-level messages about the importance of brilliance relate to the majors that young women and Black students ultimately pursue?

The answer to this question is yes, as we reported in PLOS ONE in 2016 when we analyzed anonymous student evaluations of their college instructors on RateMyProfessors.com. We found that undergraduates were nearly twice as likely to describe male professors as “brilliant” or a “genius” compared with female professors. In contrast, they used such terms as “excellent” or “amazing” equally often for men and women on the popular Web site. We determined that the overall amount of talk about brilliance and genius in the student reviews (which is a proxy for a field’s emphasis on these qualities) correlated closely with a lack of diversity in completed majors.

Origins of Stereotypes

Further investigation showed that nonacademics share similar notions of which fields require brilliance. Exposure to these ideas at home or school could discourage young members of stereotyped groups from pursuing certain careers (such as those in science or engineering) before they even set foot on a college campus.

At this point, we realized we needed to investigate the acquisition of these stereotypes. When do young people in our culture start thinking that some groups have more brilliant people in them? On the one hand, it could be that this stereotype emerges late in development, after sustained exposure to relevant cultural input (for example, media portrayals of brilliance and gender-biased expectations from parents, teachers, professors and peers). On the other hand, evidence from developmental psychology suggests that children are cultural sponges—incredibly sensitive to signals in their social environments. In fact, youngsters in the early elementary grades seem to have already absorbed the stereotypes that associate math with boys and reading with girls. From this perspective, we might expect that stereotypes about brilliance would also be acquired early in life.

To explore this idea, we asked hundreds of five-, six- and seven-year-old boys and girls many questions that measured whether they associated being “really, really smart” (our child-friendly translation of “brilliant”) with their gender. The results, which we published in 2017 in Science, were consistent with the literature on the early acquisition of gender stereotypes yet were still shocking to us. Male and female five-year-olds showed no difference in their self-assessment. But by age six, girls were less likely than boys to think that members of their gender are “really, really smart.”

Finding these stereotypes so early in childhood made us ask whether they might already begin to constrain boys’ and girls’ interests. We introduced another group of five-, six- and seven-year-olds to unfamiliar gamelike activities that we described as being “for children who are really, really smart.” We then compared boys’ and girls’ interest in these activities at each age. The results revealed no gender differences at age five but significantly greater interest from boys at six and seven years of age—which is exactly where we saw the stereotypes emerge. In addition, the children’s own stereotypes directly predicted their interest in these novel activities. The more a child associated brilliance with the opposite gender, the less interested he or she was in playing our games for “really, really smart children.” This evidence suggests an early link between stereotypes about brilliance and children’s aspirations. Over the rest of childhood development, this link may funnel many capable girls away from disciplines that our society perceives as being primarily for brilliant people.

The hard work of figuring out how best to put all this information to use—how to intervene—lies ahead of us. But a few suggestions follow pretty directly from the evidence we have so far. Minimizing talk of genius or brilliance with students and protégés may be a relatively easy and effective way of making one’s field more welcoming for members of groups that are negatively stereotyped in this respect. Given current societal stereotypes, messages that portray this trait as singularly necessary may needlessly discourage talented members of stereotyped groups. The changes may need to go a little deeper than talk, however, and tackle some of the entrenched, systemic issues that accompany a field’s fascination with brilliance. Refraining from mentioning the Beam will not help young women in philosophy if the rest of the field’s practices continue to be implicitly anchored in the idea that brilliance is all that matters.

Another key takeaway is that we may need to intervene earlier than conventional wisdom suggests. Our developmental data indicate that some of the psychological processes that work against diversity in fields that value brilliance can be traced all the way back to elementary school. Waiting until college to step in and ensure that all young people have a fair shot at finding the careers that might suit them no longer seems like the best-timed intervention—we as a society would be wise to encourage a growth perspective, as opposed to a fixed-trait mindset, in young children as well.